No. 071 Dramaturgical Analysis and Societal Critique. by John WelshPittsburgh State University
Distributed as part of the TRANSFORMING SOCIOLOGY SERIES of The Red Feather Institute, 8085 Essex, Weidman, Michigan, 48893. |
of the TRANSFORMING SOCIOLOGY SERIES of the RED FEATHER INSTITUTE for ADVANCED STUDIES IN SOCIOLOGY
|
Dramaturgical Analysis and Societal
Critique
This essay intends to uncover, add, create and clarify intellectual dimensions within dramaturgical sociology for the purpose of laying a foundation for a social critique of the dramaturgical society and, ultimately, suggesting a practice for confronting its exploitative social relations. The essential defining characteristic of the dramaturgical society is organizations controlled by class and political elites utilize the technologies of behavioral science, mass communication, marketing, advertising and the theater. With these techologies, state and business elites manage consciousness and behavior of the population for the purposes of maximizing profit and political control (Young and Massey, 1977).
Dramaturgy, as an analytical tool, enables us to understand the nature and social processes of both ancient and modern societies in which elitist hierarchies control both behavior and consciousness of those at the lower levels of hierarchy. However, understanding is only one of many uses to which dramaturgical analysis has been and can be put. There is an authentic emancipatory dramaturgy which both enlightens and politicizes those for whom it is available. Young (1991) has offered some emancipatory uses of such dramaturgy.
In this essay, we want to examine the efforts of several analysts who approach society from a dramaturgical frame of reference. These includes Erving Goffman, Hugh Duncan, Alvin Gouldner, Don Nimmo, Ivan Chapman and others. This history, we have found, reveals that on balance, the interest has been primarily to describe everyday social life as drama and to understand how individuals attempt to meet their social-psychological needs under such conditions.
In describing the dramaturgical society and understanding the everyday life of the individuals within it, dramaturgical analysts have discovered an array of exploitative and dehumanizing processes and behaviors. To some extent, these demystifying and enlightening efforts have been helpful to emanicipatory knowledge.
Yet, understanding themselves as politically neutral observers, Erving Goffman, Hugh Duncan and the others writing in this tradition have not taken the step beyond description and understanding toward a political critique of these exploitative and dehumanizing processes, with few exceptions. It remains an important task, however, that dramaturgical analysis helps to fulfill the promise of sociology in that it must provide knowledge so that individuals and groups can reflect upon and challenge the legitimacy of the structure and processes within this society (Mills, 1959).
From the point of view of critical sociology, traditional dramaturgical analysis has served, on balance, the interests of those social elites which benefit from the structural features and exploitative processes existing within dramaturgical society.
The failure to provide that social and self-knowledge which is essential to questions of the legitimacy of society is not specific to dramaturgical analysis but is one which has characterized sociology generally. Despite the fact that sociology in general has reneged on its promise of social and self- knowledge, the creation of more rational, humane and participatory societies remains the most important human project and a dramaturgical sociology sensitive to this political interest is indispensable at this point in human history.
While a variety of social analysts have sketched both the basic structural features and the formal characteristics of everyday interactions of dramaturgical society, it is important to distinguish the intellectual foundations of a critical dramaturgical analysis from its more traditional, pre-critical counterpart and to outline a strategy to create a dramaturgy which can better serve human interests in situations which require social critique as well as description and understanding.
Dramaturgy and Critical Theory.
Largely through the work of Jurgen Habermas (1970; McCarthy, 1978; Schroyer, 1973), critical social theory has delineated three forms of scientific effort which can facilitate the construction of more rational and humane societies. These three scientific forms, moreover, operate to constitute and support various social interests since they carry with them legitimations or justifications of social practices. Critical theory insists that when we adopt a theoretical perspective, such as dramaturgy, or when we present a picture of human social existence, we must always ask, whose interests are served by this theory or this depiction of social life?
Habermas maintains that theoretical perspectives and social research strategies are not neutral but have an impact upon social life in a variety of ways. Habermas further maintains that theoretical perspectives and research strategies can be grouped into three categories each with a corresponding legitimation of social practice. To outline a critical dramaturgical analysis it is helpful, first, to discuss the three forms of scientific interest outlined by Habermas and, second, to discuss how examples of the work of dramaturgical sociologists and the critics of dramaturgy fit into each of these three categories.
In delineating the three categories of scientific interests, Habermas utilizes two dimensions or two sets of criteria. These dimensions can be understood as questions that are asked about the particular perspective and research strategy. The first dimension concerns the response to how the perspective views its subject matter, people existing within a social context. Are people understood as the passive receptacles of the external stimuli of the behavioral environment or of immutable social structures? Or, are people understood as the actual or potential creators of the external behavioral environment? These questions are essentially questions of know- ledge or epistemology and they address the issue of whether people are capable of reflecting upon themselves and directing their own behavior.
So, Habermas' first dimension can be referred to as "epistemological reflexivity." Some uses of dramaturgy have been epistemologically reflexive and others have not. The second dimension concerns how the theoretical orientation views its relationship to the object of its analysis, the social world. The basic question can be stated thus: does the perspective understand itself as neutral toward or detached from the social world? Or, does it understand itself as necessarily engaged and existing in a reciprocal or interactive relationship with the social world?
These questions are essentially questions of the relationship of scientific knowledge and social being and they address the issue of what are the social and political problems and responsibilities of science. Habermas' second dimension can be referred to as "ontological reflexivity." Again, some uses of dramaturgy have demonstrated an ontological reflexivity and others have not.
The first form of scientific interest delineated by Habermas, scientism, is reflexive neither epistemologically nor ontologically. In society, the structural-functionalism of Talcott Parsons and Robert Merton, the abstracted empiricism of Paul Lazarsfeld, the exchange theory of George Homans and the conflict theories of Ralf Dahrendorf and Lewis Coser are theoretical perspectives which can be categorized appropriately as scientistic. Scientism is concerned with the production of general laws and the production and control of behavior, which contribute to the critical analysis of society primarily by producing knowledge of existing social relationships, patterns and contradictions. Scientism is conceived from the critical stand- point as that mode which produces information that assumes the interests of certainty and technical control. In sociology, the scientific perspective makes certain domain assumptions about knowledge of society, such as knowledge is inherently neutral and that the precision of the natural sciences constitutes the only appropriate model for the social sciences. The consequences of a dramaturgy interpreted in this mode will be discussed shortly. However, what is essential to note is that this form "although it conceives itself as neutral, is actually an inquiry which has the theoretical interest and societal consequence of maintaining technical control" (Schroyer, 1970:215).
Hermeneutics, the second mode of scientific effort, has provided a potent challenge to the positivistic presentation of social life by scientism. The hermeneutic approaches are concerned with the processes of the social construction of everyday life. According to Habermas and Schroyer, the hermeneutic sciences are conceived as "that mode of interpretation that yields an understanding of the social-cultural life world and that presupposes the interest of extending intersubjective understanding" (Schroyer 1970:215). The intent of the hermeneutic approaches, which in sociology include symbolic interactionism, phenomenology and ethnomethodology, is to define the object of sociological analysis from a more humanistic orientation by focusing on these intersubjective structures.
While the hermeneutic viewpoints are reflexive in an epistemological sense, as they will allow for the construction of social reality by conscious, willful human agents, they, like scientism, are not reflexive in an ontological sense. The apolitical humanistic sociologist sees his/her work as not constituting social reality but as merely and innocently apprehending, describing and reflecting social processes.
Habermas (1970:303) notes that the hermeneutic sciences have a "scientific consciousness" in that they share the methodological imperative of "describing a structured reality within the horizon of the theoretical attitude." Because they do not accept the principle that scientific knowledge has a constitutive effect on social relationships, the hermeneutic sciences have become "the positivism of the cultural and social sciences." As a consequence, the hermeneutic or interpretive perspectives cannot be conceived to be ontologically reflexive; they maintain that people are active agents but insist on the political disinterest and social disengagement of scientific practice. In order to appreciate the addition of ontological reflexivity we must move on to a consideration of Habermas' third category of scientific effort, we must move on to a consideration of critical or emancipatory sociology.
Critical social thought has consistently insisted upon an epistemological break with the more traditional and conservative social theories. Max Horkheimer (1972), one of Habermas' precursors in the Frankfort Institute for Social Research, has distinguished critical from traditional theory by noting the critical theorist's awareness of his/her social partiality.
Critical approaches reject the value-neutral and objective self-understanding of the scientistic and hermeneutic approaches by affirming the interactive, dialectical relationship between knowledge and society. Social reality, as the scientist's object of cognition, is transformed by social knowledge from a thing-in-itself to a thing-for-us. In contrast to the claims of those who argue that the sociological enterprise is an academic effort somehow existing independently of social reality and has no effect on social reality, the critical sociologist takes the perspective that sociological theory and research are intellectual definitions of the situation and, as such, cognitively structure social reality and become prescriptions for social action, whether they are so intended or not. From a critical standpoint, social reality is what it is to a great extent because of what social scientists say about it. Sociological, psychological, economic and political science definitions of the situations, thus, have a socially self-fulfilling character to them and social theory and social research must be understood as socially situated vocabularies of motive (Mills, 1940; Horton, 1966).
It must come as no surprise that critical sociologists view knowledge and definitions of reality not only emerging out of specific socio-historical milieus but also as affirming or transforming the social relationships of these socio- historical milieus. It is critical sociology which most fully grasps the dual lesson of the sociology of knowledge: knowledge has a social base and know- ledge constitutes a social base.
The third mode of science, although it finds precious little support in North American sociology, is emancipatory since it comprehends the constitutive role of social science and affirms the idea that human beings must participate in the interactional encounters in the social construction of reality or else these encounters lose their human and social character. Following in the tradition of Karl Marx, Georg Lukacs, Antonio Gramsci and Herbert Marcuse, the emancipatory thrust of science must be emphasized in those situations in which structural obstacles to full social participation have been erected. In its emancipatory modes, as Lukacs puts it, social science is the intellectual expression of social revolution. In more concrete terms, the role of research and theory in opposing and transforming capitalist commodity relationships and administered bureaucratic relationships into fully social relationships is the political expression of critical science. The emancipatory mode of science must be emphasized, for example, if an alienated objective social world is elevated above subjective human meaning in the dialectic of the social construction of reality, as Lukacs argues in his classic book, History and Class Consciousness (1971).
As is obvious, the scientistic perspective is the dominant image of social life in the median era of bureaucratic capitalism and it must not be understood as an endeavor separate from the process of the social construction of reality, but instead it must be viewed as a major form of legitimation for the social constructions of monopoly capitalism and bureaucracy. Critical sociology maintains that not only do the major orientations of social theory serve as intellectual justifications for those social categories directing the various processes of bureaucracy and monopoly capitalism, but they also help to constitute this reality in the consciousness of those who suffer under them. The task of critical sociology is to critique the theory and research of the dominant modes of sociological endeavor and in so doing challenge the legitimacy of the social reality it constitutes. The emancipatory mode of science rejects the necessity of historical modes of domination and seeks the emancipation of people from such.
Critical theory emphasizes that human emancipation is firmly grounded in processes of self and social reflection upon the legitimacy accorded the given social structural arrangements. While critical science seeks to mediate or affect human behavior by raising questions about the legitimacy of such structural arrangements, it deliberately seeks to avoid determining it. Critical knowledge must augment human self- knowledge and encourage human participation in societal processes, but it must never be used for the managerial or exploitative purposes of one social entity toward another.
Dramaturgy, as a form of sociological analysis and a legitimation of social practice, has constituted one response to the scientistic interest by claiming to provide an apprehension of the processes of social interaction in everyday life. In this positivistic interpretation, dramaturgy is utilized not as a metaphor but as an accurate, literal reflection of social life. The dramaturgical structuralism of Dan Nimmo (1974), Robert S. Perinbanayagam (1982), and George Gono (1977; 1980) are representative examples of this category of literature, as are the later works of Goffman (1974; 1976; 1981). All take the general orientation that dramatic action is built into the process of social interaction and communication.
Consequently, the dramaturgical behaviors such as impression management and role distance described by Goffman are understood as cultural universals. In addition, psychologists have attempted to "empiricize" Goffman's early dramaturgy by converting his concepts into quantified variables and his insights into hypotheses testable by experimental designs (Tedeschi, 1981). The outcome of which has been the elimination of the subjective concerns of alienation and false role performances which permeated the early work of dramaturgy in favor of quantification and generalization.
Interpreting dramaturgical structuralism through Habermas' category of scientism it is possible to discover the uses in technical control it intellectually validates. If social life is theater, if human communication is drama, then it is socially consistent that political candidates and policies, however repressive or destructive, and products, however dangerous and meaningless, can be merchandized, packaged and socially presented by organizations and the media as necessary, responsible and beneficent. While many dramaturgical scholars do not accept the scientistic orientation, those who are interested in capital accumulation and the extension of repressive control systems, such as capitalists, bureaucrats, advertisers and governmental propagandists, find in it an effective legitimation for these social practices.
Dramaturgy has contributed also to the hermeneutic interest by elaborating the mechanics through which individuals and groups create and sustain the presumption of social order through the metaphor of the theater. This hermeneutic interpretation, thus, is willing to allow for the creativity of human subjects and it affirms the essentially metaphorical nature of dramaturgy.
However, although it often draws out the alienative, exploitative dimensions of social life, Goffman's Asylums (1961a) and Stigma (1963) are excellent examples here, the hermeneutic interpretation does not understand itself as a device through which the social relations of the dramaturgical society are maintained or can be altered.
The hermeneutic interpretation of dramaturgy views humans as active, conscious willful agents who attempt to meet their material and psycho- emotional needs in oppressive, difficult or problematic social circumstances. While the scientistic interpretation of dramaturgy contributes to social emancipation by its depiction of the historically relative fact that in the dramaturgical society humans are dominated by structures, the hermeneutic interpretation contributes to social emancipation by demonstrating that the objectively existing structures of the dramaturgical society often do not meet, but instead frustrate, the needs of human actors. Probably the hermeneutic interpretations of dramaturgy comprise the bulk of the literature in dramaturgical analysis. Representative examples would include the early work of Goffman (1959; 1961a; 1961b; 1963) and the sort of articles contained in the first-rate readers such as Brissett and Edgley's Life as Theater (1974).
Despite several recent seminal efforts, the critical dimensions in dramaturgical sociology have not been developed. This work is an attempt to contribute to dramaturgical sociology and the formation of a rational and humane social life-world by developing the critical and emancipatory uses of dramaturgy. While the pre-critical dramaturgical analysis of Goffman and his followers emanates from the assumption that the theater can be used as a metaphor through which the sociologist can understand the methods which an actor or team of actors utilizes to construct social reality, the outcome of which is the effective blockage of the critical, emancipatory interest of science, the critical dramaturgical approach goes beyond the use of theater-as-metaphor and views dramaturgy as an ideology through which an actor, a team or an organization can construct a repressive and/or fraudulent social reality.
The critical interpretation of dramaturgy insists upon the dialectical relationship between society and sociological knowledge. Further, social reality must be understood as a process and sociological perspectives as contributors in this process, otherwise the constitutive role of sociological knowledge is lost and ontological reflexivity is denied. The W. I. Thomas dictum that what is conceived to be real also tends to become real must hold true for scientific knowledge as well as common sense knowledge. Thus, dramaturgical sociology itself must be understood as a technology or commodity for use in the social world.
Dramaturgy and Immanent Critique.
In a couple of recent reviews of critical literature in sociology, Robert Antonio (1981; 1983) argues that the method of immanent critique constitutes the core of critical theory and it is what unites such disparate social theorists such as Hegel, Marx, the Frankfurt School theorists, Lukacs, Gramsci and Habermas.
The method of immanent critique is appropriate to the development of a critical dramaturgy while dramaturgical analysis is a form of sociological investigation which lends itself readily to immanent critique. Stated succinctly, immanent critique allows its user to restore authenticity and actuality to false appearances by first expressing what a social formation holds itself to be and contrasting that with what in fact it is or what it is becoming. In his reformulation of the Hegelian dialectic, Marx was able to show that the false appearance of reciprocity, the false equivalence of exchange between labor and capital, was negated by the structural tendencies of capitalist society which served only to intensify human exploitation and alienation. Antonio notes, "Immanent critique attacks social reality from its own standpoint, but at the same time criticizes the standpoint from the perspective of its historical context"(1981:338). Similarly, a critical dramaturgy attempts to unmask the false presentations by contrasting the phenomenal appearance with the in-itself reality.
However, the elaboration of the opposition of the ideological claim and the real social context is oriented toward social emancipation as the ideal, the ideological claim or objective self-presentation, is converted into a weapon to transform the real. The false correspondence of the ideal and the real is elaborated in the first instance as a method of social analysis but it has a political meaning as well - to make the ideal real.
One inspiration for the critical project of scientific and social transformation and which serves also as an example of the method of immanent critique can be framed in Marx's (1970) critique of Hegel's political philosophy. In his Critique of Hegel's "Philosophy of Right" Marx noted that Hegel's comprehension and presentation of social reality, when stripped of its pantheistic mysticism, was fairly accurate as a picture of capitalist society in its emergent form. Marx then proceeded to demonstrate the contradictions in Hegel's work which would illuminate the contradictions in capitalist society. Because it was thought to be a true presentation of political reality and because it was backed up by state power, Hegel's political philosophy was an intellectual definition of the situation which served to shape social reality. Hegel's political philosophy was not merely an innocent oblation to the Prussian state and Marx did not critique it merely because he was interested in philosophy. Marx understood that the ruling ideas were the ideas of the ruling class which means, in part, that the dominant ideas about social relations benefit those who rule by legitimating their power. Thus, the emancipatory interest of science is advanced by examining the ruling ideas of an historical epoch. If dehumanizing, alienating dimensions can be demonstrated in the ruling ideas, then these will illuminate the dehumanizing, alienating dimensions of a social formation.
Critical sociology begins from the same premise of the relationship between ideological claims, intellectual definitions of the situation, and the reality of everyday human experience. The critique of dramaturgical sociology serves the emancipatory interest by providing a map for the critique of dramaturgical society, which it both reflects and has helped to constitute. Beyond the presentation of the fraudulent and repressive character of the reality of dramaturgical society, the emancipatory task of dramaturgical sociology is the critique of this reality in order to return to human agents the capacity to fully participate in the social construction of reality.
Traditional symbolic interactionism assumed a correspondence or identity of the in-itself reality and the phenomenal appearance. When George Herbert Mead, Charles Horton Cooley and Herbert Blumer state that human, social interaction consists of subjective meaning being tied to objective gestures they insist that the overt presentation is an accurate reflection of that which is hidden from public view. While dramaturgy developed out of this perspective, by no means did it claim that there are any guarantees that the presentation, the objective gesture, is a necessary reflection of the in-itself reality, subjective human meaning. Goffman's work, as one example, ought to unravel the often oppositional relationship between the self as a core entity and the self as it is presented to others. However, because his inquiry was blocked at the level of hermeneutics, Goffman appreciated the frequent opposition between the two but he succeeded only in elevating the reality of the latter and not in overcoming the opposition.
Young and Massey (1977) on the other hand, in their essay on the dramaturgical society emphasize the frequent opposition between organizational social practice as a thing-in-itself reality and as a presented reality. Opposed to Goffman, however, the critical analysis of Young and Massey enables them to suggest that a societal transformation can resolve the contradiction.
Furthermore, it has become equally clear that the phenomenal presentations can be used to mystify the reality of the thing-in-itself. It is at this juncture that critical dramaturgy becomes important. When there is a mismatch between the thing-as-presented and the thing-in-itself, then a form of fraud or distorted communication has occurred. Yet, fraud or distorted communication is not to be abstractly denounced on solely moralistic grounds. Instead, fraud serves to alienate objective and subjective reality and operates to circumvent processes of symbolic interaction, human realization and the social construction of reality. Utilizing the method of immanent critique, critical dramaturgy attempts to expose fraud in the interaction process as an alienative, exploitative process and to return to human agents the full capacity to participate in the social construction of reality. It should be apparent that this politicized form of dramaturgy bears a very close affinity to the critique of ideology and culture as it has come to be practiced in critical literature.
Viewing dramaturgy not only as a mode of sociological analysis but as a constituted social form, Young and Massey noted that large-scale organizations utilize various technologies to create false images of accountability, participation and reciprocity. In focusing on the mismatch between the presented reality and the thing-in-itself reality the work of Marx remains important partially because of its substantive content but especially because its method of immanent critique. Class societies have always developed ideologies which have functioned to mystify power relations for the purposes of maintaining asymmetrical processes in the construction of social life-worlds. Marx (1972) demystified the "reciprocity" of labor and capital by showing what the expropriation of surplus value contradicted the notion of equal exchange underlying all social relations in capitalist society. The notion of equal exchange functioned as a presentation which mystified the reality of the process of capital accumulation, since the latter depended upon the extraction of surplus value or the exploitation of the worker. In fact, the survival of capitalism depended, in part, upon the continued acceptance by the exploited workers of the "equality" or "reciprocity" of labor and capital. It is not unreasonable to expect, therefore, that those who benefit by continued capital accumulation would be interested in hiring out a cadre of technical workers which would specialize in the generation of ideologies and mystifications.
Antonio Gramsci (1971) whose very important work is only now being recognized as such by sociologists, developed further ideas which contribute to a critical dramaturgical sociology. Gramsci insightfully noted that power and domination in alienated society is maintained not only by material forces of coercion and repression but also within the consciousness of people. With the concept of "ideological hegemony" Gramsci maintained that the ruling class always seeks to legitimate its power through the creation and imposition of a worldview which stresses the need for order, authority and discipline. Consciously the ruling class attempts to subvert and emasculate the potential of revolutionary protest by subordinate social categories. Capitalism can balance its contradictions and manage its objective crises by "taking captive" the minds of those victimized by its processes of alienation and exploitation. Ideological hegemony depends upon the ruling class seizing and controlling the means of communication or the means of the production of culture. The unseen power of the ruling class is enhanced in the schools, in the family, in the workplace, by the television set and by a communicative technology which generates this worldview. The sociology of fraud, the concrete management of consciousness, as practiced by the ruling class must be made visible if society is to be transformed and the wedge between objective and subjective reality is to be removed.
Independent of the work of Gramsci, the Hegelian Marxism of Georg Lukacs (1971) affirmed the ability of the ruling class to maintain its hegemony through the control of consciousness. The central problematic of Lukacs' History and Class Consciousness emphasized that the failure of socialist revolutions centered around the Marxist failure to focus attention on the processes through which the ruling class controlled its subject populace through ideas.
The notion of "reified consciousness" as the obstacle to socialist revolution bears an affinity to a critical dramaturgical analysis in that both emphasize that the consciousness of the people is managed by an elite for the purposes of capital accumulation and political legitimacy. For Lukacs, the central aspect of the totality of a social formation lies in the connection between objective and subjective dimensions which are historically synthesized in the class consciousness of the proletariat. In the interest of maintaining the status quo of the capitalist totality a process emerges which falsely differentiates the two dimensions in that they are no longer viewed as identical. This is reification. Reification refers to the apprehension of the human-made world in terms which affirm its independence from humans. Thus, objective social relations and culture become viewed as "things" and are understood as being part of the natural world.
Reification is thus a dangerous departure from the normal social objectification of cultural artifacts and social bonds in that it ultimately inverts subject object relations and is used to create a politically and socially docile proletariat. Reification must be overcome if human agents are to participate in the social construction of reality in a reflexive, reciprocal manner. The relationship of the work of Lukacs, and that of Marx and Gramsci as well, can be summarized in the vocabulary of a critical dramaturgical analysis by saying that in class societies, regardless of technological development or the objective structures of inequality, domination and exploitation can be maintained or extended through asymmetrical prerogatives to define reality on the part of subordinate and superordinate social categories. Under capitalism the problems of capital accumulation and political legitimacy can be solved by class and organizational elites by maintaining the false impressions of reciprocity, the necessity of order, authority and discipline or the reified view of reality.
In addition to the more general critique of the scientistic and hermeneutic interpretations of dramaturgy offered by critical dramaturgy, more specific points of opposition can be derived between the pre-critical and emancipatory interests and uses of dramaturgy: As a consequence of the political sterility of the overwhelming bulk of dramaturgical sociology, there is the absence of any great moral outrage on the part of those who report on the cynical, managerial efforts to stage reality and manipulate the consciousness of human beings. This fault is a particular manifestation of the more general shortcomings of pre-critical sociology. However, the critical uses of dramaturgy involve attempts to demystify the legitimations of alienated and exploitative social life- worlds. Thus, an expression of moral outrage is a valued act, both scientifically and politically, when in response to manipulation and deceit.
Both scientistic and hermeneutic dramaturgy have failed miserably to include consideration of the larger socio-historical focus which produce the dramaturgy practices in everyday life by individual actors and large-scale organizations. The analyst who asks what brought dramaturgy about will be disappointed by pre-critical dramaturgical literature. The ahistorical perspective of dramaturgy would make one think that the dramaturgy employed in everyday life is a transcendental human dilemma and that either original sin, nature or hidden social structures are responsible for it. The critical view, on the other hand, understands dramaturgy as a phenomenon dependent upon various social and historical conditions. The recurrent crises of capital accumulation (O'Connor, 1973) and of political legitimacy (Habermas, 1974), as well as the rise of predominantly Gesellschaft social relations (Tonnies, 1957), loom as paramount in this regard. The connection between dramaturgy and its macro-social base must be examined.
Pre-critical uses of dramaturgy have failed also to critique constructed social reality from a perspective of the moral values claimed within that social reality. The method of immanent critique emphasizes the mismatch between the public claims and the public performances of social formations. To the extent that a mismatch exists, social formations are alienated and must be critiqued from the perspective of the public claim. The phenomenological imperative of understanding social formations on their own terms is crassly overridden by conservative dramaturgical analysis which seeks instead to understand things on its terms, which entails the inflexible imposition of a theatrical model upon human subjects. The critical view does not seek to control human behavior by imposing an artificial model on social life. Instead, the critical emphasis is to mediate human behavior by providing knowledge so that people can reflect upon the legitimacy of obstacles to full participation in the social construction of reality.
An important specific criticism of dramaturgy is the absence of any coherent theoretical context with which to give dramaturgical analysis a meaning context. The critical uses of dramaturgy accepts that a valid distinction can be made between authentic and fraudulent social formations and presentations of self. Pre-critical dramaturgy either obfuscates this distinction or collapses the two into the latter so that it cannot delineate the boundaries of where it can and cannot be applied legitimately. While the dramaturgy described by structuralist and hermeneutic analysts is a social device that is probably always utilized in fraudulent social formations, it is not true that it is always utilized in authentic social formations. In not understanding this distinction, pre-critical dramaturgy has not only mystified the variability of social relations, it has overlooked some very exciting uses of dramaturgy, for example, the dramaturgy of undistorted communications or of authentic social performances.
A final specific criticism of dramaturgical analysis is its unconcern with a systematic explanation of how dramaturgy could amplify the human condition. Life without dramaturgy would be one without joy, pride, delight, surprise and enchantment.
Dramaturgical sociology must be pointed to the processes by which human beings set themselves apart from the natural world. The use of drama to distinguish the profane world of nature from the scarred world of humanity and community, of status and solidarity is abused when dramaturgy is used for commercial or managerial purposes, or simply as another commodity.
While these criticisms are largely valid, note that they do not negate the importance of dramaturgical analysis. Instead, they condemn a dramaturgy that is divorced from the emancipatory interest. These criticisms should form the basis around which a critical dramaturgical analysis can be constituted. Dramaturgical analysis has far too much to offer as a mode of understanding and transforming social life to continue as a dilettantish excursion into sunshine sociology and it is too important to be written off by serious radicals as necessarily an exercise in counterrevolution. Transformed into a critical mode, dramaturgy's contributions as a revolutionary project cannot be ignored.
The Constitution of a Critical Dramaturgy.
Bearing in mind that in the present socio-historical context critical dramaturgy understands itself as being in opposition to the manipulative, coercive technologies utilized by bureaucratic and class elites to manage problems of capital accumulation and political legitimacy, it is important to review efforts which have appeared in recent sociological literature attempting to subject dramaturgy to a radical critique. The intention is to evaluate these efforts as adequate critiques for the transformation of the dramaturgical society and to further specify the method of a critical dramaturgical analysis.
In his The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology, Alvin Gouldner (1970:378- 390) conceives of Goffman's early dramaturgical sociology as symptomatic of the crisis of Western sociology. Gouldner basically equates Western sociology with the structural-functionalism of Talcott Parsons, and its crisis lies primarily in its inability to provide an adequate theory of social change which has undermined somewhat its utility as a legitimation for the capitalist Welfare State, which must use change and planning strategies to cope with an increasing surplus population and the crisis of underconsumption. Gouldner senses both the critical and conservative potential in Goffman's dramaturgy. He notes that Goffman's dramaturgical sociology, in a sense, is a rebellion against the system's level of analysis, which seems to preclude the comprehension of social reality as the result of an ongoing process of human interaction. In other words, Goffman's dramaturgy can be viewed as a hermeneutic response to the scientism of structural-functionalism.
Gouldner also sees critical potential in Goffman's hermeneutic sociology of fraud precisely because it legitimates the individual's prerogative to con the system. Dramaturgy, according to Gouldner, has critical dimensions because it certainly passes no negative moral judgment on tax evaders, or asylum inmates who manipulate their jailers. On balance, however, Gouldner sees a greater degree of conservative potential in Goffman's dramaturgy. Primarily, Gouldner is worried that dramaturgy reduces humans to mere commodities and he effectively ties the work of Goffman to the "organization man" as a legitimation of "getting kicks" out of things as they are, since the transformation of society is defined out of the realm of possibility by the conservative dramaturgical ideologists. Of course, the technology of conning the system is not equally available to all individuals throughout all social strata. Thus, dramaturgy is a technology of rebellion primarily for the "new bourgeoisie" and socially it functions as a technology that legitimates the reduction of persons and selves to the status of mere commodities.
While Gouldner is certainly to be applauded for unmasking the "rebellious" dimensions in Goffman's dramaturgy and demonstrating the link between dramaturgy and the "commodity fetishism" of monopoly capitalism, his work must be understood as only a starting point in the development of an immanent critique of dramaturgical society. Gouldner is worried about the demise of structural-functionalism and he deals with dramaturgy in a briefly critical manner only as a stepping stone to his personal response to the crisis. This is his "reflexive" sociology, which turns out to be reflexive in only an epistemological sense. The critical dramaturgist responds that Gouldner has missed the mark in constituting a crisis in structural-functionalism, which is perhaps a historically obsolete sociological legitimation for the processes of the particular phase of capitalism it attempted to apprehend and maintain. The critical dramaturgical sociologist counters that perhaps the crisis of capitalist society and Western sociology is now being managed by the adoption of dramaturgy as a sociology and a technology for legitimating this particular phase of capitalist domination. If so, the significant task for those sociologists wanting to contribute to the construction of a fully rational and humane and participatory social reality is the critique of dramaturgical sociology and the dramaturgical society it has helped to constitute.
In a thoughtful critique of the dramaturgical sociology of Goffman, Ivan Chapman (1974:45-52) demonstrates the departures of dramaturgy from a fully social, fully participatory model of social action based on symbolic interaction in which each actor possesses the prerogative to contribute to the meaning of a socially significant symbol. Utilizing a Meadian framework of symbolic interaction at the dyadic level of social analysis, Chapman notes that both actors are free to exercise both their "I" and "me" capabilities in an ongoing process of defining the situation. Goffman's model, Chapman argues, is the symbolic management of one person by another. In the case of the social dyad, the actor utilizing the technology of dramaturgy feels no social constraint by the mediating socially significant symbol, but feigns his/her "I" act of personal desire so that it appears to be based on social meaning and in so doing evokes in the other a "me" response based on the acceptance in good faith of the "expression given off" as though it were an "expression given" or an expression based on mutual social meaning. The person acting in good faith is reduced to an object, a "me" in the Median sense, and can be used, exploited, objectified or taken captive by the exploiting actor. The exploiting actor only appears to shift to a "me" while retaining all "I" prerogatives to define the situation. With the loss, evasion or circumvention of the reciprocity of symbolic processes of interaction, the dyad is destroyed as a fully human, social and participatory processes of reality construction.
Chapman objects to Goffman's dramaturgical reduction of social life to episodic con games and he has demonstrated the departures of Goffman's symbolic management emphasizing good faith and reciprocity. Yet, as an exemplar for a fully critical dramaturgy Chapman's opposition of "Social Interaction versus the Appearance of Social Interaction" falls somewhat short. First, because he chooses to deal with Goffman's dramaturgical sociology and not with the reality of the dramaturgical society, Chapman does not develop an immanent critique. His critique is one which emphasizes the social consequences of Goffman's dramaturgy and he rejects Goffman on the basis of dramaturgy's legitimation of symbolic management. What is essential to an immanent critique, however, is that Goffman's dramaturgy be accepted as an adequate depiction of the nature of social reality. A one-sided focus on Goffman's dramaturgy, excluding a focus on upon the social reality of dramaturgical practice, fails to develop an opposition between the presented reality and the in-itself reality. Goffman's depiction of social life is dismissed by Chapman as inaccurate and the ideological social presentations of good faith, authenticity and reciprocity, the qualities of Median symbolic interactionism are accepted as adequate depictions of life under modern monopoly capitalism. Thus, Chapman confuses the ideological claim and the real characteristics of social life in this historical context.
Chapman's failure to address the social ontology of the dramaturgical society leads to another problem. Chapman senses the contradiction between "social interaction" and the "appearance of social interaction" as a universal moral dilemma. He does not ground the dramaturgical behaviors he finds repugnant in relative and concrete socio-historical circumstances. Chapman fails to pose the question: in what kinds of societies does the dramaturgical departure appear or become significant?
From a critical standpoint, the dramaturgical exploitation of one actor by another must be situated in social formations which are historically relative and which serve the interests of one social category at the expense of another social category. For example, the rise of capitalism as a mode of economic production and distribution, with its elevation of secondary, Gesellschaft group relations, undoubtedly contributed to the emergence and legitimation of the individual and team exercise of a dramaturgical technology. After all, the social reality of capitalism insists that persons are to treat others and expect to be treated as commodities. Yet, the relationship between capitalism and its consequent elevation of Gesellschaft relations and a dramaturgical technology escapes Chapman's analysis. Therefore, he cannot conclude that dramaturgical exploitation can be overcome by the overthrow of the social formations making it a possible and a legitimate technology in interpersonal relations. Instead of dismissing Goffman's legitimation of con artistry, Chapman universalizes it.
Ultimately, Chapman's critique of Goffman, like that of Gouldner, becomes nothing more than a moralistic lament with nothing but dread for the "social" reality of the present and dread for the future. His failure to establish a fully critical dramaturgy must be tied to his choice of critiquing dramaturgy solely on epistemological grounds, which is an important undertaking, but which is an obstacle to the critique of the social reality of dramaturgical exploitation. Showing departures in Goffman's work from a fully human, fully social and fully participatory paradigm is not sufficient. The departures must be demonstrated also in the everyday lives of the inhabitants of the alienated reality of the dramaturgical society.
Beyond Gouldner and Chapman, the additional task of the critical dramaturgist is the overthrow of those socio-historical formations permitting and creating a dramaturgical society and its socio-historical legitimations. The repressive, exploitative uses of dramaturgy must not be confronted on epistemological grounds solely; instead, the development and encouragement of political activities through which the dramaturgical society can be overthrown and the full capacity of people to participate in the social construction of everyday life constitute the additional central interests of a critical dramaturgical sociology.
REFERENCES
Antonio, Robert J. 1983 "The Origin, Development and Contemporary Status of Critical Theory." The Sociological Quarterly 24(3):325-351.
1981 "Immanent Critique as the Core of Critical Theory: Its Origins and Developments in Hegel, Marx and Contemporary Thought." British Journal of Sociology 32(3):330-345.
Brissett, Dennis and Charles Edgley 1975 Life as Theater: A Dramaturgical Sourcebook. Chicago: Aldine.
Chapman, Ivan 1974 "Social Interaction versus the Appearance of Social Interaction." International Review of History and Political Science May:45-52.
Goffman, Erving 1959 The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books.
1961a Asylums: Essays on the Social Situations of Mental Patients and Other Inmates. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books.
1961b Encounters. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Co.
1963 Stigma. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
1974 Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience. New York: Harper Colophon Books.
1976 Gender Advertisements. New York: Harper Colophon Books.
1981 Forms of Folk. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Gouldner, Alvin 1970 The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology. New York: Basic Books.
Gonos, George 1977 "'Situation' versus 'Frame': The 'Interactionist' and the 'Structuralist' Analyses of Everyday Life" in Jason Ditton, ed., The View from Goffman. New York: St. Martin's Press.
1980 "The Class Position of Goffman's Sociology: Social Origins of an American Structuralism" in Jason Ditton, ed., The View from Goffman. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Gramsci, Antonio 1971 Prison Notebooks. New York: International Publishers.
Habermas, Jurgen 1971 Knowledge and Human Interests. Boston: Beacon Press.
1970 "Toward a Theory of Communicative Competence" in Hans Peter Dreitzel, ed., Recent Sociology, No. 2. New York: MacMillan Company.
1970 "On Systematically Distorted Communication." Inquiry 13:205- 218.
1974 Legitimation Crisis. Boston: Beacon Press.
1979 Communication and the Evolution of Human Society. Boston: Beacon Press. Horkheimer, Max
1972 Critical Theory. New York: The Seabury Press.
Horton, John 1966 "Order and Conflict Theories of Social Problems as Creating Ideologies." American Journal of Sociology 71(6).
Lukacs, Georg 1971 History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
McCarthy, Thomas 1978 The Critical Theory of Jurgen Habermas. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Marx, Karl 1970 Critique of Hegel's "Philosophy of Right." Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
1972 "Capital: Selections" in Robert Tucker, ed., The Marx-Engels Reader. New York: W. W. Norton.
Mills, C. Wright 1940 "Situated Actions and Vocabularies of Motive." American Sociological Review 5:904-913.
1959 The Sociological Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press.
Nimmo, Dan 1976 "The Drama, Illusion and Reality of Political Images" in J. Combes and M. Mansfield, eds., Drama in Life. New York: Hastings House.
O'Connor, James 1973 The Fiscal Crisis of the State. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Perinbanayagam, Robert S. 1982 The Karmic Theater: Self, Society and Astrology in Jaffna. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. Schroyer, Trent
1970 "Toward a Critical Theory of Advanced Industrial Society" in Hans Peter Dreitzel, ed., Recent Sociology, No. 2. New York: MacMillan.
1973 The Critique of Domination. Boston: Beacon Press. 1AB Tedeschi, James T., ed.
1981 Impression Management Theory and Social Psychological Research. New York: Academic Press.
Tonnies, Ferdinand 1957 Community and Society. East Lansing, MI: Michigan State University Press.
Young, T. R. 1978 "The Division of Labor in the Construction of Social Reality: Critical Dimensions in Dramaturgical Analysis." The Red Feather Institute: Transforming Sociology Series.
Young, T. R. and Garth Massey 1977 "The Dramaturgical Society: A Macro-Analytic Approach to Dramaturgical Analysis." Qualitative Sociology 1:78-98.