Vol. 1. Introduction to Postmodern Criminology.
Constitutive Criminology: An Overview of an Emerging Postmodernist School*
No. 001
Distributed as part of the Red Feather Institute Postmodern Criminology Series. The Red
Feather Institute, 8085 Essex, Weidman, Michigan, 48893.
Constitutive criminology is an integrated critical approach to the analysis of crime and its control. It has emerged in the past 10 years through our collaborative efforts to transcend the limits of both modernist and postmodernist thought on matters of crime and justice (Henry and Milovanovic, 1991; 1994; 1996; Milovanovic and Henry, 1991; Barak, 1993; 1994a; 1994b; 1997b). It surpasses the limited and often reductionist causative models of modernist positivist empiricism and abandons the search for causal factors. However, constitutive criminology also moves beyond the nihilism, subjectivism and defeatism found in skeptical postmodernism (Schwartz and Friedrichs, 1994). It is an affirmative postmodernism, recognizing the co-production of crime by human subjects, and by the social and organizational structures that humans develop and endlessly (re)build. The essence of the constitutive argument is that crime and its control cannot be separated from the totality of the discursively ordered, structural and cultural contexts in which it is produced.
Drawing on contributions from postmodernism, feminism, marxism, semiotics, psychoanalysis, social constructionism, structuration theory, chaos theory, and communications theory, constitutive criminology provides a genealogical investigation of crime, criminologists, and criminology in their relations with human subjects, law and social order. This new criminology addresses crime's interwoven connections with the wider complexity of social relationships through a synoptic analysis whereby crime is related to the "symbolic," the "imaginary," and the "real." It is an open-ended approach proposing that human subjects are responsible for actively creating their world with others, a world which simultaneously acts back, shaping the subject's own identity. Through social interaction involving language and symbolic representations, people identify and evaluate differences, construct categories, organize their activities to reflect those categories, and share a belief in the reality of that which is constructed. This shared belief gives order to otherwise chaotic states while it also recursively constructs their lives. By investing energy in socially constructed realities, human subjects are not only shaped, but they also help shape the world around them.
Constitutive criminology thus furnishes a dynamic conception of social structure as a virtual and infinitely revisable society where human subjects dynamically and contingently interact. Consistent with its own analysis, constitutive criminology is an unfinished, emergent articulation of these interrelations as they develop, merge, and continue to transform one another.
The constitutive criminological vision of the human subject is open to both human diversity and specificity, as well as being contingently formed so as to adjust to emerging renditions of subjectivity in historical contexts (Butler, 1990). To capture this contingent formation, constitutive criminology uses the term "recovering subject." The human subject is seen as "recovering" because it is always striving for a final and certain state of being, but never arrives. Such a vision is an important first step in developing a framework that allows for the richness of human potentiality, without foreclosing its endless possibilities. The recovering human subject always has the potential to escape the cages of its own and others' constructions, not least by investing energy in new ones.
An emergent, contingent, and revisable notion of human subjectivity and behavior also influences constitutive criminology's conception of criminals and victims. The human subject-as-offender is viewed as an "excessive investor" in the power to dominate others. Such "investors" put energy into creating and magnifying differences between themselves and others. This investment of energy disadvantages, disables and destroys others' human potentialities. The human subject-as-victim is viewed as a special case of the "recovering subject," still with untapped human potentiality but with a damaged faith in humanity. Victims are more entrenched, more disabled, and suffer loss. Victims "suffer the pain of being denied their own humanity, the power to make a difference. The victim of crime is thus rendered a non-person, a non-human, or less complete being" (Henry and Milovanovic, 1996: 116).
Each of the "subjects" of these multiple interrelations of crime may simultaneously be viewed as "objects" for domination. As objects, human subjects represent co-produced reflections of the multiple signifiers that are connected in chaotic and continuous ways. At the same time these signifiers remain with some degree of self-referentiality (autopoietic). In other words, they replicate and expand, drawing energy from their environment to strengthen their own internal processes. Nowhere is this self-inflating expansion more evident than in law.
Constitutive criminology rejects modernist images of law as an independent entity; autonomous law is myth (Fitzpatrick, 1992). It argues that we need to transcend the view that law is the linear product of cultural consensus, structural forces, structural conflicts, interactive relations or system processes. This vision distracts from addressing the complexities involved in the subject-society-law relationship. In contrast, constitutive criminology views law, like other institutional structures, as semi- autonomous, mutually constituted through social relations and discursive misreading (Santos, 1987). Law's semi-autonomy derives from its constitution through the discursive processes of non-state normative orders with which it is interrelated and interwoven. These dynamic normative orders provide the formative contexts for the production of new legal and social forms. Here we begin to see how "social control," taken as the plethora of non-state normative orders, are a necessary part of the ideological process whereby object-like qualities of law are created and sustained. It is the very distinction between "law" and "social control" that sustains law as a discrete entity. Investment in the construction of this distinction gives law its appearance of autonomy and is constitutive of its power.
The significance of the interconnectedness of law with other social forms is that law will inevitably contain the self-same expressions of power that create the "formative contexts" of crimes that are subsequently omitted from definition (Unger, 1976). Law recursively constitutes the suffering, and pain of "crime" in more insidious forms, such as when the powerful benefit from otherwise perceived "free" contractual relations. This is not the same, for example, as saying corporate interests shape the law in order to be immune from prosecution which renders them free to create harm. Rather, it is saying that corporations, as "excessive investors" in power, constitute law to reflect the legitimacy of their power and the illegitimacy of the power of others. Uncritically accepting legal definitions of crime reconstitutes the power that is crime's harm. Law is not merely a passive definer of crime. It is a maker of crime, the manifestation of which provides sustenance to its classificatory schema of crimes. This is because it conceals some agent's (person, agency, institution, state, "constitutive interrelational-set") harms by institutionalizing and legitimizing the power relations whose continuance brings harm. For example, "`conjugal violence' is a product of a crimino-legal practice which stands in as proxy for the violence of the marriage relation. There is then a legal culture of violence in which conjugal homicide takes place. Violence resides in the house of law, the house of marriage" (Young and Rush, 1994: 166). As Young and Rush argue, it is necessary to abandon the "smooth surface of the universal victim" for this sacrifices too much of its particular in silence. Law designed to uphold power differentials cannot protect against harm; it frames its construction (Young and Rush, 1994). This is in the sense of the pervasive hidden crimes of domination that Bourdieu describes as "symbolic violence," "the violence which is exercised on a social agent with his or her complicity" (Bourdieu and Wacquant (1992: 167).
So too, with the unitary notion of "crime." Crime is a socially constructed and discursively constituted legal category. It is a violent categorization of the diversity of human conflicts and transgressions into a single category "crime." It melts differences reflecting the multitude of variously motivated harms into a single entity or series of legal abstractions, such as "violent crime" or "property crime." As such the conventional and legalistic conceptions of crime are celebrations of homogeneity that sustain and perpetuate the violence of crime's power relations. Whether one is referring to victims experiencing harm, or to offenders experiencing ennui, rage, rationalization, seduction, or dehumanization, constitutive criminology argues that unequal power relations, built on the construction of difference, provide the conditions that define crime as harm. Thus constitutive criminology redefines crime as the harm resulting from investing energy in relations of power that involves pain, conflict and injury. People in relations taken to be "crimes," are in relations of inequality. They are, as discursively constituted human subjects, being disrespected; reduced from what they are, prevented from becoming what they might be. Thus we define crime as "the expression of some agency's energy to make a difference on others, and it is the exclusion of those others, who in the instant are rendered powerless to maintain or express their humanity" (Henry and Milovanovic, 1996: 116). This agency may be comprised and energized by people, social identities (men, women, etc.), groups, parties, institutions, the state or even constitutive interrelational-sets. Crime manifests a disrespecting power. Indeed, "crimes are nothing less than moments in the expression of power, such that those who are subjected to them are denied their own contribution to the encounter and often to future encounters, are denied their worth . . . Crime then is the power to deny others their ability to make a difference." (Henry and Milovanovic, 1996: 116).
The activities of many of those in the institutions in western industrial society are premised on the exercise of power over others; the witting or unwitting denial of others' right to make a difference. This is the root of why capitalism is criminogenic, why ours is a violent society. It is also why Party hierarchy state socialism is criminogenic. The activities of those who construct occasions for the deliverance of power is crime. It is crime because it takes from people any present dignity and, further, represses their attempt to change. Thus a constitutive view of crime includes much of what currently stands for business practices, governmental policies, and hierarchical social relations. It includes a lot of what occurs in family life. It is why sexual harassment and violence against women (whether in emotional torment or physical beating from either spouse to the other or to dependents) are crimes. It is especially why child abuse is a crime. Indeed, it is why emotional terror by employers over employees through at-will employment is a crime. Finally, it is why several of the actions or inactions of government agencies, such as neglect of health and safety in the workplace, are also crimes and why homelessness is a crime. These arenas are each premised upon the inequality of power relations that allow some to build their freedom on the backs of others denied.
As a discursive construction, crime has various capabilities of being expressed within given discourses. It also undergoes translation/transformation between discourses as is the case of the lower class defendant or other marginalized, disempowered, and disenfranchised groups before the court, a translation often unreflective of the complexities of existence. This is the violence of language. As an alternative to the legalistic definition of crime, our postmodernist definition focuses on harm inflicted in all its guises and would certainly include the "violence of language" (Lecercle, 1990), particularly how disenfranchised, disempowered, and marginalized have been denied expressive forms for their desires and yearnings, that is to say, how their voices are denied (Freire, 1985; Aronowitz and Giroux, 1991; Giroux, 1992).
Thus, in contrast to existing legal and modernist definitions of crime our definition of crime is specific, but historically contingent, and includes victim categories that allow us to be aware of the changing nature of the emerging social constructions whose relations of power are relations of harm. Harm results "from any attempt to reduce or suppress another's position or potential standing through the use of power that limits the other's ability to make a difference" (Henry and Milovanovic, 1996: 13). For this reason constitutive criminologists find it helpful to identify two aspects of the relations of domination that characterize crime. "Crimes of reduction" and "crimes of repression" refer to power differentials and to hierarchical relations that reinforce both types of harm. Harms of reduction occur when offended parties experiences a loss of some quality relative to their present standing. They could have property stolen from them, but they could also have dignity stripped from them as in acts of hate against discredited groups.
Harms of repression occur when offended parties experience a limit or restriction preventing them achieving a desired position or standing. They could be prevented from achieving a career goal because of sexism or racism, or meet a promotional "glass ceiling." Considered along a continuum of deprivation, a continuous variable, harms of reduction or repression may be based on any number of constructed differences. As presently constituted in late twentieth century western industrial societies harms cluster around the following constructed differences: economic (class, property), gender (sexism), race and ethnicity (racism, hate), political (power, corruption), morality, ethics (`avowal of desire'), human rights, social position (status/prestige, inequality), psychological state (security, well being), self-realization/actualization, biological integrity, etc. Whatever the construction, these are harms either because they move the offended away from a position or state they currently occupy, or because they prevent them from occupying a position or state that they desire, whose achievement does not deny/deprive another.
As can be seen, unlike the narrowly defined modernist definitions of crime, the constitutive definition is capable of accommodating an infinite range of harms as experienced, for example, by the present sites of race, class, and gender domination. Our definition of crime as "the exercise of the power to deny others their own humanity" needs to be anchored to the specificities of endless substitutable, existent and emergent social constructions. It is through these constructions that humanity is constituted and along these discursive dimensions it takes shape. Only in such a way can we be continuously aware of the relations of crime and of the social space needed to replace these with less harmful forms. But because law can only be reconstituted (because of its interrelations with other social orders) by reconstituting the relations of other social forms with which it is interrelated, merely changing law's definition of crime to include more victim types is, on its own, futile. Rather, to change the social construction of harm it is necessary to change the social forms and their implied power relations so that harm is not carried under the guise of law, in the expression of power over others. To both comprehend and counteract the harmful outcomes of such interrelations, constitutive criminology points to the need to transcend modernist culturally produced images of crime and punishment and to see them more appropriately as mutually constituted through social relations and discursive (mis)readings.
Assuming that crime, criminals, and victims are dynamic, indeterminable, dialectical, and interrelational phenomena, embedded in the discursive cultural co-production of the subject-society-law relationship, constitutive criminology argues that "causation" in the positivist, predictive, determinist, and linear sense, does not exist. Constitutive criminology, claims that the very notion of "cause" is problematic, and sets out to examine the unexplored territories of probability and criminological theory. Modern theories of crime causation have failed not because they have been unable to correctly advance the causal ordering among variables, but because no such correct causal ordering exists in the first place.
Importantly, while not totally abandoning the notion of causation, constitutive criminology presents an assemblage of causality from the perspectives of "mutual influences," "structural couplings," "relational sets," "psychoanalytic semiotics," "gendered analyses," and "chaotic transformations." Consistent with an affirmative postmodern position, constitutive criminology draws inspiration from dialectical assumptions, arguing that crime is not so much caused as discursively constructed through human processes of which it is one. Hence, "crime is the ongoing, recursively produced outcome of numerous different contexts of interrelationship, wherein human subjects progressively lose sight of their productive contribution, and increasingly invest in that which they produce to the point of some becoming excessive investors and others victims of denial, reduction, [and] repression" (Henry and Milovanovic, 1996: 170). In the non-linear chaotic world, neither "criminals" nor "crimes" are static concepts or objective entities. They only appear this way when positivistic criminologists "freeze" the social reality of either for the purposes of trying to identify "independent" and "dependent" variables. Nevertheless, in terms of a soft determinist, neo-positivist, and postmodern integration, "cause" may refer to the influences and variations that occur through the interrelations of discourses, ideologies, imaginations, unconsciousnesses, histories, and political economies, all of which are never fully separated as discrete entities. Instead of singular "factors" or "multiple factors" causing crime, constitutive criminology sees crimes as harms that are the recurrent, co-produced outcomes of constitutive interrelational sets (or "COREL" sets).
Given this interlocking and interconnected perspective of crime and society, what has constitutive criminology to say with regards to questions of justice policy and practice techniques? The object-like qualities of crime, law, and punishment are created and sustained by discursive policies and practices, and can be transformed to reflect the expansive possibility engendered by our recovering human subject. In short, constitutive criminology calls for a justice policy of replacement discourse. This should substitute for a policy of criminal justice founded on deficient conceptions of the problem which are co-constitutive of the ongoing vitality of crime. In terms of diminishing the harm experienced from all types of crime (street, corporate, state, hate etc.), constitutive criminology talks of "liberating" discourses that seek transformation of both the prevailing political economies and the associated practices of crime and social control.
As part of a policy of "replacement discourse" on crime and justice, constitutive criminology welcomes theoretical contradictions and behavioral contingencies. These provide discursive opportunities for reinvesting in the ordering of disorders and for recovering those subjects overinvested in the "harms of reduction" or the "harms of repression." In other words, as a "post" postmodern integration, constitutive criminology has policy ramifications for criminal justice, media production, and mass culture. In particular, it advocates an "empowered democracy" (Unger, 1987) through newsmaking and peacemaking criminologies, social judo, radical refraction and cultural pluralism. Constitutive theory is rooted in, yet striving to be free from, the material conditions of an apparently inevitable linear unfolding of historical processes. Hence, the constitutive approach to criminology calls for a transpraxis of incompleteness, for a movement toward a process that seeks to liberate the human spirit while at the same time not sowing the seeds of additional harm and destruction.
In applied terms, constitutive criminology seeks to integrate "objective" and "subjective" interpretations of crime and social control. Conceptually it aspires to do this by connecting scholarly analyses and popular discourses as they intersect in the virtual reality of such mass- mediated themes as: crime and crime-fighting, criminals and victims and criminalization and victimization. Specifically, constitutive criminology recognizes the co-responsibility that criminologists have for crime and crime control that is reproduced (or reduced) daily. As such, constitutive criminologists actively engage in the developing praxis of newsmaking criminology that confronts the prevailing myths, stereotypes, and constructions associated with the common images of crime and justice, as a means of transforming both the discourses and practices surrounding crimes of reduction and repression (Barak, 1994a; 1997a; 1997b).
References
Aronowitz, S. and H.A. Giroux. 1991. Postmodern Education. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Barak, G. 1993. "Media, Crime and Justice: A Case for Constitutive Criminology" Humanity and Society, 17 (3): 272-96.
Barak, G. (ed) 1994a. Media, Process and the Social Construction of Crime: Studies in Newsmaking Criminology. New York: Garland.
Barak, G. 1994b "Between the Waves: Mass-Mediated Themes of Crime and Justice" Social Justice, 21(3): 133-47.
Barak, G. 1997a. "Newsmaking Criminology and O.J. Simpson: An Ethnographic Portrait." In G. Barak (ed) Representing O.J.: Murder, Criminal Justice and Mass Culture. Albany, NY: Harrow and Heston.
Barak, G. 1997b. Integrating Criminologies. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.
Bourdieu, P. and L.J.D. Wacquant. 1992. An Invitation to Reflexive Sociology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Butler, J. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Fidelity. New York: Routledge.
Fitzpatrick, P. 1992. The Mythology of Modern Law. London: Routledge. Freire, P. 1985. The Politics of Education. South Hadley, MA: Bergin and Garvey.
Giroux, H. 1992. Border Crossings. New York: Routledge. Henry, S. and D. Milovanovic. 1991. "Constitutive Criminology." Criminology 29 (2): 293-316.
Henry, S. and D. Milovanovic. 1994. "The Constitution of Constitutive Criminology: A Postmodern Approach to Criminological Theory." In D. Nelken (ed.), The Futures of Criminology. London: Sage.
Henry, S. and D. Milovanovic. 1996. Constitutive Criminology: Beyond Postmodernism. London: Sage.
Lecercle, J.J. 1990. The Violence of Language. New York: Routledge. Milovanovic, D. and S. Henry. 1991. "Constitutive Penology." Social Justice 18 (3): 204-24.
Santos, B.S. 1987. "Law: a Map of Misreading. Toward a Postmodern Conception of law," Journal of Law and Society, 14: 279-302.
Schwartz, M. D., and D. O. Friedrichs. 1994. "Postmodern Thought and Criminological Discontent: New Metaphors for Understanding Violence," Criminology, 32(2): 221-46.
Unger, R.M. 1976. Law in Modern Society. New York: Free Press.
Unger, R.M. 1987. False Necessity. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Young, A. and Rush, P. 1994. "The Law of Victimage in Urban Realism: Thinking Through Inscriptions of Violence," in D. Nelken (ed.), The Futures of Criminology. London: Sage. pp. 154-72.